Response to Mercer’s “Two ways”
David White
Mark Mercer argues that academic freedom is valuable because it promotes the
generation of new knowledge through academic research and assists with spreading
knowledge through educating students. Because academic freedom is essential to
both the production and dissemination of knowledge, universities have a strong
obligation to protect and promote it. So far we are in complete agreement. But
Mercer goes further to argue for the intrinsic value of academic freedom and
that such value provides universities with a stronger obligation to protect it.
On this point, we disagree.
Mercer argues for a conception of the university as one comprised of people who
value free inquiry not just for its good effects, but for its own sake.
Intellectual autonomy, he argues, has value over and above how it contributes to
the production and dissemination of knowledge. There are two problems with this
perspective, however. Firstly, I see no reason to think that all or even most
academics do value academic freedom for intrinsic reasons. If most or even just
many academics only value academic freedom because they value creating and
spreading knowledge, then it is hard to see why a university should have an
obligation to protect that freedom for reasons of intrinsic value.
Secondly, even if he is right that all academics value freedom because they
regard it as having intrinsic value it still provides the university no
compelling reason to protect it. There are a lot of things that academics might
regard as having intrinsic value. Participating in sports and listening to good
music might be two such things. But the fact that members of the university
community value those things intrinsically gives the institution no obligation
to provide opportunities to participate in sports or to listen to music. It is
not the job of the university as an institution to provide academics with things
they enjoy. The university has a specific mandate to create knowledge and to
educate students and so it is only the instrumental value of academic freedom
that gives it an obligation to protect it.
Mercer has one additional worry about only valuing academic freedom for
instrumental reasons. He argues that in cases where we might judge that by
limiting academic freedom we will actually help the production and spread of
knowledge (say, by stopping research or teaching that seems to promote bigotry)
viewing academic freedom only instrumentally provides a basis for limiting it in
some cases. While I agree that arguments like this are sometimes made, I
disagree with the idea that they are ever sound arguments.
History teaches us well that ideas that were once regarded as obviously false
and even pernicious have come to be viewed as true today. The earth does in fact
revolve around the sun. Homosexuals are not in fact morally depraved and
mentally ill. History teaches us that the ideas it might seem obviously
beneficial to suppress today could well turn out to be found to be true
tomorrow. Just as in the judicial system we believe it better that ten guilty
people go free than one innocent person be convicted, in the pursuit of
knowledge it is better that some pernicious ideas be allowed to be defended than
to silence some truths we have yet to discover.
If some academics value the academic life for intrinsic reasons, then that is
good for them. But it gives the university no additional reason to promote
academic freedom. The instrumental value that such freedom provides is more than
enough justification for a complete defense of full academic freedom without
exception.
David
White is a graduate student in philosophy at the University of Calgary.
`